Aristotle on Philosophia

Research output: Contribution to journalArticle

Abstract

Aristotle uses philosophia (and philosophos, philosophein, philosophôs, sumphilosophein, philosophêteon) in at least ten senses across his oeuvre, as this first study of every instance in his writings reveals. Irrespective of the specific approaches of its practitioners, philosophia may be, for example, an exercise of cleverness; or leisurely study; or the desire to know; or the pursuit of fundamental explanation; or a historically extended discipline. This variety allows us to go some way in reconstructing the complex attitude Aristotle had toward a culturally specific practice in which he located himself and soon helped develop into a specialized discipline. Another benefit is that it allows us to clarify the argumentative method in his Protrepticus, which depends on several senses of philosophia. It also puts up obstacles to determining whether, for example, Aristotle believes philosophia is an epistêmê.

Original languageEnglish (US)
Pages (from-to)339-360
Number of pages22
JournalMetaphilosophy
Volume50
Issue number3
DOIs
StatePublished - Apr 1 2019

Fingerprint

Aristotle
Pursuit
Fundamental
Exercise

All Science Journal Classification (ASJC) codes

  • Philosophy

Cite this

Moore, Christopher Robert. / Aristotle on Philosophia. In: Metaphilosophy. 2019 ; Vol. 50, No. 3. pp. 339-360.
@article{226723888ffa4c0cbe75032d538eeaa4,
title = "Aristotle on Philosophia",
abstract = "Aristotle uses philosophia (and philosophos, philosophein, philosoph{\^o}s, sumphilosophein, philosoph{\^e}teon) in at least ten senses across his oeuvre, as this first study of every instance in his writings reveals. Irrespective of the specific approaches of its practitioners, philosophia may be, for example, an exercise of cleverness; or leisurely study; or the desire to know; or the pursuit of fundamental explanation; or a historically extended discipline. This variety allows us to go some way in reconstructing the complex attitude Aristotle had toward a culturally specific practice in which he located himself and soon helped develop into a specialized discipline. Another benefit is that it allows us to clarify the argumentative method in his Protrepticus, which depends on several senses of philosophia. It also puts up obstacles to determining whether, for example, Aristotle believes philosophia is an epist{\^e}m{\^e}.",
author = "Moore, {Christopher Robert}",
year = "2019",
month = "4",
day = "1",
doi = "10.1111/meta.12360",
language = "English (US)",
volume = "50",
pages = "339--360",
journal = "Metaphilosophy",
issn = "0026-1068",
publisher = "Wiley-Blackwell",
number = "3",

}

Aristotle on Philosophia. / Moore, Christopher Robert.

In: Metaphilosophy, Vol. 50, No. 3, 01.04.2019, p. 339-360.

Research output: Contribution to journalArticle

TY - JOUR

T1 - Aristotle on Philosophia

AU - Moore, Christopher Robert

PY - 2019/4/1

Y1 - 2019/4/1

N2 - Aristotle uses philosophia (and philosophos, philosophein, philosophôs, sumphilosophein, philosophêteon) in at least ten senses across his oeuvre, as this first study of every instance in his writings reveals. Irrespective of the specific approaches of its practitioners, philosophia may be, for example, an exercise of cleverness; or leisurely study; or the desire to know; or the pursuit of fundamental explanation; or a historically extended discipline. This variety allows us to go some way in reconstructing the complex attitude Aristotle had toward a culturally specific practice in which he located himself and soon helped develop into a specialized discipline. Another benefit is that it allows us to clarify the argumentative method in his Protrepticus, which depends on several senses of philosophia. It also puts up obstacles to determining whether, for example, Aristotle believes philosophia is an epistêmê.

AB - Aristotle uses philosophia (and philosophos, philosophein, philosophôs, sumphilosophein, philosophêteon) in at least ten senses across his oeuvre, as this first study of every instance in his writings reveals. Irrespective of the specific approaches of its practitioners, philosophia may be, for example, an exercise of cleverness; or leisurely study; or the desire to know; or the pursuit of fundamental explanation; or a historically extended discipline. This variety allows us to go some way in reconstructing the complex attitude Aristotle had toward a culturally specific practice in which he located himself and soon helped develop into a specialized discipline. Another benefit is that it allows us to clarify the argumentative method in his Protrepticus, which depends on several senses of philosophia. It also puts up obstacles to determining whether, for example, Aristotle believes philosophia is an epistêmê.

UR - http://www.scopus.com/inward/record.url?scp=85063887135&partnerID=8YFLogxK

UR - http://www.scopus.com/inward/citedby.url?scp=85063887135&partnerID=8YFLogxK

U2 - 10.1111/meta.12360

DO - 10.1111/meta.12360

M3 - Article

AN - SCOPUS:85063887135

VL - 50

SP - 339

EP - 360

JO - Metaphilosophy

JF - Metaphilosophy

SN - 0026-1068

IS - 3

ER -